Косвенные речевые акты в современном английском языке

Разделы Иностранные языки
Тип

Курсовая

Формат Microsoft Word
Язык Английский
Загрузить архив:
Файл: ref-19287.zip (63kb [zip], Скачиваний: 45) скачать

CONTENTS

   INTRODUCTION…………….……………………………………….3

1. INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS: FORM VERSUS FUNCTION…………5

2. WHY DO SPEAKERS HAVE TO BE INDIRECT?…………………..7

2.1. The cooperative principle…………………………………………….7

2.2. The theory of politeness ……………………………………………...8

3. HOW DO HEARERS DISCOVER INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS   

   AND “DECIPHER” THEIR MEANING?…………………………….10

3.1. The inference theory………………………………………………...10

3.2. Indirect speech acts as idioms?…………………………………...…12

3.3. Other approaches to the problem……………………………………13

4. ILLOCUTIONS OF INDIVIDUAL UTTERANCES WITHIN A   

    DISCOURSE………………………………………………………….14

          5.INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS IN ENGLISH AND UKRAINIAN……..16

          6.EXAMPLES OF INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS IN MODERN

   ENGLISH DISCOURSE………..…………………………………….18

6.1. Fiction………………………………………………………………18

6.2. Publicism……………………………………………………………20

6.3. Advertising………………………………………………………….21

6.4. Anecdotes…………………………………………………………...21

          7. INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS AS A YARDSTICK OF COMMUNI-

             CATIVE MATURITY AND MUTUAL UNDERSTANDING …..….23

             CONCLUSIONS……….……………………………………………..25

   РЕЗЮМЕ……………….…………………………………………….27

   LITERATURE….…………………………………………………….28

INTRODUCTION

                                                            “A great deal can be said in the study of                    

                                                             language without studying speech acts,  

                                                             but any such purely formal theory is

                                                             necessarily incomplete. It would be as if

                                                            baseball were studied only as a formal

                                                            system of rules and not as a game.”

                                                                     John Rogers Searle

In the late 1950s, the Oxford philosopher John Austin gave some lectures on howspeakers “do things with words” and so invented a theory of “speech acts”[10, 40] which now occupies the central place in pragmatics (pragmatics is the study of how we use language to communicate in a particular context). Austin highlighted the initial contrast between the constative and the performative.While constatives describe a state of affairs, performatives (explicit and implicit) have the potential to bring about a change insome state of affairs. Classical examples of performatives include the naming of a ship, the joining oftwo persons in marriage, and the sentencing of a criminal by an authorised person. Austin distinguished between the locution of a speech act (the words uttered),its illocution (the intention of the speaker in making the utterance) and its perlocution(its effects, intended or otherwise).Whereas constatives typically have truth conditions to comply with, speech acts mustsatisfy certain “felicity conditions” in order to count as an action: there must be a conventional procedure; the circumstances and people must be appropriate;the procedure must be executed correctly and completely; often, the persons must have the requisite thoughts, feelings, etc.

John Austin’s theory of speech acts was generalized to cover all utterances by a student of Austin's, John Rogers Searle [43, 69]. Searle showed that we perform speech acts every time we speak. For example, asking “What's the time?” we are performing the speech act of making a request.  Turning an erstwhile constative into an explicit performative looks like this: “It is now ten o’clock” means “I hereby pronounce that it is ten o’ clock in the morning.”

In such a situation, the original constative versus performative distinction becomes untenable: all speech is performative. The important distinction is not between the performative and the constative, but between the different kinds of speech acts being performed, that is between direct and indirect speech acts.Searle's hypothesis was that in indirect speech acts, the speaker communicates the non-literal as well as the literal meaning to the hearer.This new pragmatic trend was named   intentionalism because it takes into account the initial intention of the speaker and its interpretation by the hearer.

Actuality of research:

The problem of indirect speech acts has got a great theoretical meaning for analysis of the form/function relation in language: the same form performs more than one function.  To generate an indirect speech act, the speaker has to use qualitatively different types of knowledge, both linguistic and extralinguistic (interactive and encyclopaedic), as well as the ability to reason[45, 97]. A number of theories try to explain why we make indirect speech acts and how we understand their non-literal meaning, but the research is still far from being complete.

The practical value of research lies in the fact that it is impossible to reach a high level of linguistic competence without understanding the nature of indirect speech acts and knowing typical indirect speech acts of a particular language.  

The tasks of research:

1) analysis of the theories on indirect speech acts;     

2) finding out why interlocutors generate indirect speech acts instead of saying exactly what they mean;

3) comparing typical indirect speech acts in English and in Ukrainian;

4) providing examples of indirect speech acts in various communicational situations.

The object of research is a speech act asa communicational action that speakers perform by saying things in a certain way in a certain context.

The subject of research is an indirect speech act as the main way in which the semantic content of a sentence can fail to determine the full force and content of the illocutionary act being performed in using the sentence.

Methods of research include critical analysis of scientific works on the subject, analysis of speech of native English speakers in various communicational situations, analysis of speech behavior of literary personages created by modern British and American writers.

        

1.INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS: FORM VERSUS FUNCTION

                                                    “Communication is successful not when        

                                                      hearers recognize the linguistic meaning of the

                                                      utterance, but when they infer the speaker's          

                                                      meaning from it.”

                                                                         Dan Sperber and Deidre Wilson

Most of what human beings say is aimed at success of perlocutionary acts, but because perlocutionary effects are behavioural, cognitive, or emotional responses they are not linguistic objects. What linguists can properly look at, however, are the intentions of speakers to bring about certain perlocutionary effectswhich are called illocutionary intentions.

The basis of a speech act is the speaker’s intention to influence the hearer in a desired way. The intention can be manifested and latent. According to O.G. Pocheptsov [13,74], latent intentions cannot be linguistically analyzed while manifested intentions can be divided into evident and inferable. The illocutinary intention of indirect speech acts is inferable.

Three broad illocutionary categories are normally identified – a statement, a question and a command/request - having typical realisations in declarative,interrogative and imperative verb forms. But sometimes the syntactic form of a sentence is not a good guide to the act it is performing. In indirect speech acts the agreement between the intendedfunction and the realised form breaks down, and the outward(locutionary) form of an utterance does not correspond with the intendedillocutionary force of the speech act which it performs [37, 263].In indirection a single utterance is the performance of one illocutionary act by way of performing another. Indirect speech acts have two illocutionary forces [45, 195].

Searle’s classical example of an indirect speech act is the utterance “Can you pass the salt?” Without breaking any linguistic norms we can regard it as a general question and give a yes/no answer. But most often hearers interpret it as a request.   Likewise, the utterance “There's a fly in your soup” may be a simple assertion but, in a context, a warning not to drink the soup. The question “What's the time?” might, when one is looking for an excuse to get rid of an unwelcome guest, be intended as a suggestion that the guest should leave.  Analogously, the statement “I wouldn't do this if I were you” has the congruent force of an imperative: “Don't do it!”

In his works Searle gives other interesting examples of indirect speech acts:Why don’t you be quiet? It would be a good idea if you gave me the money now. How many times have I told you (must I tell you) not to eat with your fingers? I would appreciate it if you could make less noise. In some contexts these utterances combine two illocutionary forces and sound idiomatic, even though they are not idioms in the proper sense of the term.Each utterance contains an imperative (secondary illocution) realized by means of a question or a statement (primary illocution).

Paul Griceillustratesindirectness by the following utterances [4, 22]: “There is a garage around the corner” used to tell someone where to get petrol, and “Mr. X's command of English is excellent, and his attendance has been regular”, giving the high points in a letter of recommendation. A simple example of an indirect speech act gives B.Russel: “When parents say ‘Puddle!’ to their child, what they mean is ‘Don’t step into it!’ [41, 195].These areexamples in which what is meant is not determined by what is said.

We can make a request or give permission by way of making a statement, e.g. by uttering “I am getting thirsty.” or “It doesn't matter to me.” We can make a statement or give an order by way of asking a question, such as “Will the sun rise tomorrow?” or “Can you clean up your room?”When an illocutionary act is performed indirectly, it is performed by way of performing some other one directly.

It has been found that indirect expressives, directives and representatives compose the most numerous group of indirect speech acts [11, 23].

The study of indirect speech acts has mostly dealt with requests in various guises. Jerrold M. Sadock identified some exotic species: “whimperatives” - indirect requests in the form of a question, e.g. “Can't you (please) do something?” and “Do something, will you?”;“queclaratives” -the speaker directly questions and indirectly makes an assertion:“Does anyone do A any more?” meaning "Nobody does A any more"; “requestions” are quiz questions to which the speaker knows the answer, e.g. Columbus discovered America in ...?[42, 168].

Summarizing, we can say that indirection is the main way in which the semantic content of a sentence can fail to determine the full force and content of the illocutionary act being performed in using the sentence.

2.WHY DO SPEAKERS HAVE TO BE INDIRECT?

                                                   “Everything that is worded too directly nowadays                                     

                                                   runs the risk of being socially condemned.”

                                                                                                   Ye. Klyuev

2.1. The cooperative principle

         An insight into indirectness is based on the Cooperative Principle developed by Paul Grice [4, 14-76]: language users tacitly agree to cooperate by making their contributions to the conversationto further it in the desired direction. Grice endeavoured to establish a set of general principles explaining how language users convey indirect meanings (so-called conversational implicatures, i.e. implicit meanings which have to be inferred from what is being said explicitly, on the basis of logical deduction). Adherence to this principle entails that speakers simultaneously observe 4 maxims:

1) Maxim of Quality:

- Do not say what you believe to be false.

      - Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence.

2) Maxim of Relevance:

     - Be relevant.

3) Maxim of Quantity:

     - Make your contribution as informative as required.

     - Do not make your contribution more informative than is required.

4) Maxim of Manner:

     - Avoid obscurity of expression.

     - Avoid ambiguity.

     - Be brief.

     - Be orderly.

This general description of the normal expectations we have in conversations helps to explain a number of regular features in the way people say things. For instance, the common expressions"Well, to make a long story short" or "I won't bore you with the details" indicate an awareness of the maxims of quantity and manner. Because we assume that other speakers are following these maxims, we often draw inferences based on this assumption.

At one level, cooperative behaviour between the interactants means that the conversational maxims are being followed; but at another and more important level, cooperative behaviour still operates even if the conversational maxims are apparently broken.For instance, when the speaker blatantly and openly says something which appears to be irrelevant and ambiguous (flouts the maxims of relevance and manner), it can be assumed thats/he really intends to communicate something which is relevant and unambiguous, but does so implicitly:

“ - I don't suppose you could manage tomorrow evening?

- How do you like to eat?

- Actually I rather enjoy cooking myself.” [J. Fowles]

The second remark, instead of being a direct answer (a statement), is a question formally not connected with the first remark.The maxims of relevance and manner are flouted. The inferable implicature is: “Yes, I can.”Analogously, the implication of the third remark is inferred: “I invite you to have dinner at my place.”                                                                     

If we were forced to draw only logical inferences, life would be a lot more difficult. Conversations would take longer since we would have to say things which reasonable language-users currently infer.   

Searle adds one more conversational maxim [45, 126]: “Speak idiomatically unless you have a reason not to.” He exemplifies this maxim like this: if we say archaically “Knowest thou him who calleth himself Richard Nixon?” (not idiomatically), the utterance will not be perceived as a usual question “Do you know Richard Nixon?”

An important difference between implicatures and what is said directly is that the speaker can always renounce the implicatures s/he hinted at. For example, in “Love and friendship” by A.Lourie the protagonist answers to a lady asking him to keep her secret: “A gentleman never talks of such things”. Later the lady finds out that he did let out her secret, and the protagonist justifies himself saying: “I never said I was a gentleman.”

Implicatures put a question of insincerity and hypocrisy people resort to by means of a language (it is not by chance that George Orwell introduced the word “to double speak” in his novel “1984”). No doubt, implicatures are always present in human communication.V.Bogdanov notes that numerous implicatures raise the speaker’s and the hearer’s status in each other’s eyes: the speaker sounds intelligent and knowledgeable about the nuances of communication, and the hearer realizes that the speaker relies on his shrewdness. “Communication on the implicature level is a prestigious type of verbal communication. It iswidely used by educated people: to understand implicatures, the hearer must have a proper intellectual level.” (Богданов 1990:21).

The ancient rhetorician Demetrius declared the following: “People who understand what you do not literally say are not just your audience. They are your witnesses, and well-wishing witnesses at that. You gave them an occasion to show their wit, and they think they are shrewd and quick-witted. But if you “chew over” your every thought, your hearers will decide your opinion of their intellect is rather low.”   (Деметрий 1973:273).

2.2. The theory of politeness

Another line of explanation of indirectness is provided by asociolinguistic theory of politeness developed in the late 1970s. Its founder Geoffrey Leech introduced the politeness principle: people should minimize the expression of impolite beliefs and maximize the expression of polite beliefs [36, 102]. According to the politeness theory, speakers avoid threats to the “face” of the hearers by various forms ofindirectness, and thereby “implicate” their meanings rather than assert them directly. The politeness theory is based on the notion that participants are rational beings with two kinds of “facewants” connected with their public self-image [26, 215]:

• positive face - a desire to be appreciated and valued by others; desire for approval;

• negative face - concern for certain personal rights and freedoms, such asautonomy to choose actions, claims on territory, and so on; desire to beunimpeded.

Some speech acts (“face threatening acts”) intrinsically threaten the faces. Ordersand requests, for instance, threaten the negative face, whereas criticism and disagreementthreaten the positive face. The perpetrator therefore must either avoid such actsaltogether (which may be impossible for a host of reasons, including concern forher/his own face) or find ways of performing them with mitigating of their face threatening effect. For example, an indirectly formulated request (a son to his father) “Are you using the car tonight?” counts as a face-respecting strategy because it leaves room for father to refuse by saying “Sorry, it has already been taken (rather than the face-threatening “You may not use it”). In that sense, the speaker’s and the hearer’s faces are being attended to.

Therefore, politeness is a relative notion not only in its qualitative aspect(what is considered to be polite), but in its quantitative aspect as well (to what degree various language constructions realize the politeness principle). Of course there are absolute markers of politeness, e.g. “please”, but they are not numerous. Most of language units gain a certain degree of politeness in a context.

3. HOW DO HEARERS DISCOVER INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS AND “DECIPHER” THEIR MEANING?

It has been pointed out above that in indirect speech acts the relationship between the words being uttered and the illocutionary force is often oblique. For example, the sentence “This is a pig sty” might be used nonliterally to state that a certain room is messy and filthy and, further, to demand indirectly that it be cleaned up. Even when this sentence is used literally and directly, say to describe a certain area of a barnyard, the content of its utterance is not fully determined by its linguistic meaning-in particular, the meaning of the word “this” does not determine which area is being referred to.

How do we manage to define the illocution of an utterance if we cannot do that by its syntactic form? There are several theories trying to answer this question.

3.1. The inference theory

The basic steps in the inference of an indirect speech act are as follows [37, 286-340]:

I. The literal meaning and force of the utterance are computed by, and available to, the participants.The key to understanding of the literal meaning is the syntactical form of the utterance.

II. There is some indication that the literal meaning is inadequate (“a trigger” of an indirect speech act).

According to Searle, in indirect speech acts the speaker performs one illocutionary act but intends the hearer to infer another illocution by relying on their mutually shared background information, both linguistic and nonlinguistic, as well as on general powers of rationality and inference, that is onillocutionary force indicating devices[43, 73].   The illocutionary point of an utterance can be discovered by an inferential process that attends to the speaker's prosody,the context of utterance, the form of the sentence, the tense and mood of verbs, knowledge of the language itself and of conversational conventions, and general encyclopaedic knowledge. The speaker knows this and speaks accordingly, aware that the hearer - as a competent social being and language user - will recognize the implications[32, 41]. So, indirectness relies on conversational implicature: there is overwhelming evidence that speakers expect hearers to draw inferences from everything that is uttered.It follows that the hearer will begin the inferential process immediately on being presented with the locution. Under the cooperative principle, there is a convention that the speaker has some purpose for choosing this very utterance in this particular context instead of maintaining silence or generating another utterance. The hearer tries to guess this purpose, and in doing so, considers the context, beliefs about normal behaviour in this context, beliefs about the speaker, and the presumed common ground.

The fact that divergence between the form and the contents of an utterance can vary within certain limits helps to discover indirect speech acts: an order can be disguised as a request, a piece of advice or a question, but it is much less probable as a compliment.

III. There are principles that allow us to derive the relevantindirect forcefrom the literal meaning and the context.

Searlesuggests that these principles can be stated within his theory of felicity conditions forspeech acts [44, 38].

For example, according to Searle’s theory, a commandor a request has the following felicity conditions:

1. Asking or stating the preparatory condition:

Can you pass the salt?The hearer's ability to perform an action is being asked.

Literally it is a question; non-literally it is a request.

2. Asking or stating the propositional content:

You're standing on my foot. Would you kindly get off my foot?

Literally it is a statement or a question; non-literally it is a request.

3. Statingthe sincerity condition:

I'd like you to do this for me.

Literally it is a statement; non-literally it is a request.

4. Stating or asking the good/overriding reasons for doing an action:

You had better go now. Hadn't you better go now?Why not go now?

Literally it is a statement or a question; non-literally it is a request.

5. Asking if a person wants/wishes to performan action:

Would you mind helping me with this?Would you mindif I asked you if you could write me a reference?

Literally it is aquestion; non-literally it is a request (in the last example an explicit directive verb is embedded).

All these indirect acts have several common features:

1.Imperative force is not part of the literal meaning of these sentences.

2.These sentences are not ambiguous.

3.These sentences are conventionally used to make requests. They often have "please" at end or preceding the verb.

4. These sentences are not idioms, but are idiomatically used as requests.

5. These sentences can have literal interpretations.

6. The literal meanings are maintained when they question the physical ability:Can you pass the salt? - No,it’s too far from me. I can’t reach it.

7. Both the literal and the non-literal illocutionary acts are made when making a report on the utterance:

The speaker: Can you come to my party tonight?

The hearer: I have to get up early tomorrow.

Report: He said he couldn't come. OR:He said he had to get up early next morning.

A problem of the inference theory is that syntactic forms with a similar meaning often show differences in the ease in whichthey trigger indirect speech acts:

a)Can you reach the salt?

b) Are you able to reach the salt?

c) Is it the case that you at present have the ability to reach the salt?

While (a) is most likely to be used as a request, (b) is less likely, and (c) is highly unlikely, although they seem to expressthe same proposition.

Another drawback of the inference theory is the complexity of the algorithm it offers for recognizing and deciphering the true meaning of indirect speech acts. If the hearer had to pass all the three stages every time he faced an indirect speech act, identifying the intended meaning would be time-consuming whereas normally we recognize each other’s communicative intentions quickly and easily.

3.2. Indirect speech acts as idioms?

Another line of explanation of indirect speech acts was brought forward by Jerrold Sadock [42, 197]. According to his theory,indirect speech acts are expressions based on an idiomatic meaning added to their literal meaning (just like the expression “to pushup daisies” has two meanings: “to increase the distance of specimens of Bellis perennis from the center of theearth by employing force” and “to bedead”).Of course, we do not have specific idioms here, but rathergeneral idiom schemes. For example, the scheme “Can you + verb?”is idiomatic for commands and requests.

However, the idiomatic hypothesis is questionable as a general strategy. One problem is that a reactionto an indirect speech act can be composite to both the direct and the indirect speech act, e.g.

The speaker:Can you tell me the time?

The hearer:Yes, it’s three o’clock.

We never find this type of reaction to the literal and the idiomatic intepretation of an idiom:

The speaker:Is he pushing the daisies by now?

Hearer 1: Yes/no (the idiomatic meaning is taken into account).

Hearer 2: Depends what you mean. As a gardener, yes (the literal meaning is taken into account).

Another problem is that there is a multitude of different (and seemingly semanticallyrelated) forms that behave in a similar way:

a)Can you pass me the salt?

b) Could you pass me the salt?

c)May I have the salt?

d) May I ask you to pass the salt?

e) Would you be so kind to pass the salt?

f) Would you mind passing the salt?

Some of these expressions are obviously semantically related (e.g. can/could, would you be so kind/wouldyou mind), and it seems that it is this semantic relation that makes them express the same indirect speechact. This is different for classical idioms, where the phrasing itself matters:

a)topush the daisies “to be dead” vs. topush the roses

b)tokick the bucket “to die” vs. to kick the barrel.

Hence, a defender of the idiom hypothesis must assume a multitude of idiom schemes, some of which areobviously closely semantically related.

Summarizing, we can say that there are certain cases of indirect speech acts that have to be seen as idiomatized syntactic constructions (for example, English why not-questions.) But typically, instances of indirectspeech acts should not be analyzed as simple idioms.  

3.3. Other approaches to the problem

The difference of the idiomatic and inference approaches can be explained by different understanding of the role of convention in communication. The former theory overestimates it while the latterunderestimates it, and both reject the qualitative diversity of conventionality.Correcting this shortcoming, Jerry Morgan writes about two types of convention in indirect speech acts [39, 261]:conventions of language and conventions of usage. The utterance “Can you pass the salt?” cannot be considered as a regular idiom(conventions of language), but its use for an indirect request is undoubtedly conventional, i.e. habitual for everyday speech that is always characterized by a certain degree of ritualization.

In accordance with this approach the function of an indirect speech act is conventionally fixed, and an inference process is not needed.   Conventions of usageexpress what Morgan calls “short-circuited implicatures”: implicatures that once were motivated by explicitreasoning but which now donot have to be calculated explicitly anymore.

There is an opinion that indirect speech acts must be considered as language polysemy, e.g. “Why not + verb?” construction serves as a formal marker of not just the illocutive function of a question, but of that of a request,e.g. “Why not clean the room right now?”

According to Grice and Searle, the implicit meaning of an utterance can always be inferred from its literal meaning. But according to the relevance theory developed by Sperber and Wilson [46, 113], the process of interpretation of indirect speech acts does not at all differ from the process of interpretation of direct speech acts. Furthermore, it is literal utterances that are often marked and sound less natural than utterances with an indirect meaning. For example, the utterance “She is a snake.”having an implicit meaning sounds more natural than “She is spiteful.”Exclamatory utterances “It’s not exactly a picniс weather!” and“It’s not a day for cricket!” soundmore expressive and habitual than the literalutterance “What nasty weather we are having!”The interrogative construction expressing a request “Could you put on your black dress?” is more customary than the performative: “I suggest that you should put on your black dress.”  

To summarize: there is no unanimity among linguists studying indirect speech acts as to how we discover them in each other’s speech and “extract” their meaning. Every theory has got its strong and weak points, and the final word has not yet been said.

4.ILLOCUTIONS OF INDIVIDUAL UTTERANCES WITHIN

A DISCOURSE

Speech act theories considered above treat an indirect speech act as the product of a single utterance based on a single sentence with only one illocutionary point - thus becoming a pragmatic extension to sentence grammars.In real life, however, we do not use isolated utterances: an utterance functions as part of a larger intention or plan. In most interactions, the interlocutors each have an agenda; and to carry out the plan, the illocutions within a discourse are ordered with respect to one another.   Very little work has been done on the contribution of the illocutions within utterances to the development of understanding of a discourse.

As Labov and Fanshel pointed out, “most utterances can be seen as performing several speech acts simultaneously ... Conversation is not a chain of utterances, but rather a matrix of utterances and actions bound together by a web of understandings and reactions ... In conversation, participants use language to interpret to each other the significance of the actual and potential events that surround them and to draw the consequences for their past and future actions.”(Labov, Fanshel 1977: 129).

Attempts to break out of the sentence-grammar mould were made by Labov and Fanshel [35], Edmondson [29], Blum-Kulka, House, and Kasper [24]. Even an ordinary and rather formal dialogue between a customer and a chemist contains indirectness (see table 4.1).

                                                                                 Table 4.1

Indirect speech acts of an ordinary formal dialogue

PRIVATEParticipant

Utterance

Indirect speech acts

Customer

Do you have any

Actifed?

    Seeks to establish preparatory condition for

    transaction and thereby implies the intention to

    buy on condition that Actifed is available.

Chemist

Tablets or linctus?

     Establishes a preparatory condition for the

     transaction by offering a choice of product.

Customer

Packet of tablets,

please.

     Requests one of products offered, initiates

     transaction. In this context, even without  

     “please”, the noun phrase alone will function as

      a requestive.

Chemist

That'll be $18.50.

   A statement disguising a request for payment to

    execute   the transaction.

Customer

OK.

    Agrees to contract of sale thereby fulfilling

t   buyer's side of the bargain.

Chemist

Have a nice day!

    Fulfills seller's side of the bargain and

   concludes interaction with a conventional farewell.

Discourse always displays one or more perlocutionary functions. Social interaction predominates in everyday chitchat; informativenessin academic texts; persuasiveness in political speeches; and entertainment in novels. But many texts combine some or all these functions in varying degrees to achieve their communicational purpose. For instance, although an academic text is primarily informative, it also tries to persuade readers to reach a certain point of view; it needs to be entertaining enough to keep the reader's attention; and most academic texts try to get the reader on the author’s side through social interactive techniques such as use of authorial we to include the reader.

The genre of the text shapes the strategy for its interpretation: we do not expect nonliterality when reading medical prescriptions. For every genre there is an illocutionary standard. For example, a letter of recommendation is an alloy of declarations and expressives. A request added to it converts it into a petition whereas a detailed list of facts from the person’s life turns it into a biography. In canonized texts, lack of “moulds” has a significant pragmatic load.

The illocutionary standard of a text depends on the communicative situation and macrocontext. For example, in “The Centaur” by John Updike there is an obituary whose indirect meaning is much wider than the literal meaning (chapter 5 of the novel).

On the whole, the contribution of the illocutions of individual utterances to the understanding of macrostructures within texts is sorely in need of study.

5.INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS IN ENGLISH AND UKRAINIAN

Pragmatic research reveals that the main types of speech acts can be found in all natural languages. Yet, some speech acts are specific for a group of languages or even for a certain language. For instance, the English question “Have you got a match?” is a request while the Ukrainian utterance“Чи маєте Ви сірники?” possesses two meanings: either the speaker is asking you for matches or offering them to you. Only the utterance “У Вас немає сірників?”having interrogatory intonation andstressed “немає” is unambiguously a request.

Offering advice, the Ukrainians prefer not to use modal verbs(могти, хотіти) that would make up an indirect speech act. Preference is given to direct speech acts of advice.   

Seeing off guests, the Ukrainians often use causative verbs, e.g. “Заходіть! Телефонуйте! Пишіть!”This communicative behaviour often provokes an inadequate reaction of foreigners: instead of “Дякую!”prescribed by the Ukrainian speech etiquette they say: “With great pleasure!” or ask “When exactly should I come? What for?”

Mikhail Goldenkov describes a typical indirect speech act used in US public transport [3,82]. If a passenger wants to get off a crowded bus, s/he should not directly question the passengers blocking the way if they are getting off or not (like it is usually done in Ukraine). A direct speech act would be taken as meddling in other people’s personal matters.    A request to make way must be disguised as a statement: “Excuse me, I am getting off” or as a question in the first person: “Could I get off please?”

Indirect speech acts must always be taken into account when learning a foreign language. In many cases they make the communicative center and sound much more natural than direct speech acts. In particular, at English lessons in Ukraine much attention is given to direct inverted questions. Furthermore, often only such questions are considered to be correct, and as a result students get accustomed to conversations reminding a police quest: “Have you got an apartment?”, “Where does your father work?”, etc. However, when asking for information, native speakers do not often use direct speech acts because they are not suitable from the point of view of speech etiquette. To master the art of conversation, students must be able to use indirect declarative questions, e.g. “I’d like to know if you are interested in football” or “I wonder if we could be pen-pals”, etc.

Native English speakers often say that English-speaking Ukrainians sound too direct. As a result, the hearer feels pressure that can cause a communication failure.I remember my husband selecting books to borrow in a public library of Montreal, Canada. He put aside the books he chose and left them unattended for a minute to go to another bookshelf. Meanwhile another reader came by and took some of my husband’s books. Seeing that, my husband came up to the man and said: “Please put the books back”.The man looked offended. Definitely, he did not expect a direct speech act. He took it as a command threatening his “negative face”. My husband made a communicational mistake. An indirect speech act was the only thing appropriate in the situation. He should have said something like “Excuse me, but I am borrowing those books.”It would have been a request disguised as a statement.

English lessons for the Ukrainians must include Tips for making English less direct, i.e.special information on how to “soften” directness of speech using indirect speech acts, for example:“Try topresent your view as a question, not as a statement.Say: “Wouldn’t that be too late?” instead of “That will be too late.”

6.EXAMPLES OF INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS IN MODERN ENGLISH DISCOURSE

6.1. Fiction

Literature is often compared to a mirror reflecting life. Writers strive to make their personages sound natural, and utterances of literary personages can be linguistically analyzed just like speech of real people. Here are some examples of indirect speech acts generated by heroes of works written by modern British and US authors.

a) In the short story “The Life Guard” by John Wain young Jimmy Townsend works as a beach lifeguard. One morning he wants to get rid of an unwelcome visitor in his hut at the beach and asks him to quit using an indirect speech act (a representative with the illocutionary force of a directive): “I’m going swimming now. I have to keep in practice.” The visitor, however, does not understand the implication and answers: “I am not stopping you.”  Jimmy tries another indirect speech act: “I have to leave the hut empty.” The implication dawns on the visitor, but he is not sure: “You mean nobody is allowed in the hut?” Jimmy uses an indirect speech act to invite the visitor to join him for a swim (a request disguised as a question): “Why don’t you come in swimming with me if you want something to do?”

To prove his efficiency as an instructor, Jimmy wants to teach swimming to an old fat lady. The woman wants Jimmy to leave her alone, but being polite, avoids a command and uses representatives with the illocutionary force of a directive: “The water is cold?”; “It’s the first time I am on the beach this year”; “I’ll never swim the Channel, that I do know.”

Scared that he will be fired because no one needs a lifeguard at a safe beach, Jimmy plans to arrange a fake rescue. He asks his former schoolmate to pretend drowning: “I want you to go in swimming, pretend to get into trouble, wave to me, and I’ll swim out and tow you back to shore.” The boy declines Jimmy’s idea using an indirect speech act (a question with the illocutionary force of a statement): “What d’you think I am, daft?”

b)In Thorton Wilder’s novel titled "Heaven’s my destination" a young man named Mr.Brush asks Mr. Bohardus, a forensic photographer, to sell a photograph:

“- There, now, I guess, we got some good pictures.

- Do you sell copies of these, Mr.Bohardus?

- We're not allowed to, I reckon. Leastways there never was no great demand.

- I was thinking I could buy some extra. I haven't been taken for more than two years. I know my mother would like some.

Bohardus stared at him narrowly.

- I don't think it shows a good spirit to make fun of this work, Mr.Brown, and I tell you I don't like it. In fifteen years here nobody's made fun of it, not even murderers haven't.

- Believe me, Mr.Bohardus, said Brush, turning red, "I wasn't making fun of anything. I knew you made good photos, and that's all I thought about."

Bohardus maintained an angry silence, and when Brush was led away refused to return his greeting”.

The question “Do you sell copies of these, Mr.Bohardus?” has another meaning, that of a compliment. Compliments have a restricted sphere of usage, and the photographer’s negative reply showed that under the circumstances it was not appropriate to compliment a policeman.The compliment was rejected in a friendly manner. But Brush broke the standard scheme of an indirect speech act and turned a compliment into a literal request. The policeman was insulted: he thought that Brush mocked at him. Brush tried to make amends, but to no avail. Brush violated the communicative convention, and his words were interpreted as an affront.

c) Earl Fox, the protagonist of the novel“Live with lightning” composed by Mitchell Wilson, is a famous physicist aged 50. His social status is high, but he falls out of love with his science and feels inner emptiness and despair. The author uses a rhetoric question to describe the first fit of Fox’s indifference to physics:

“Realization had come slowly, against his reluctance. He was listening to a paper being read, and he found himself asking “Who cares?” It was the first open admission that curiosity was dead.”

Rhetoric questions are pseudoquestions because the speaker knows the answer and does not ask for information. On the contrary, a rhetoric question conveys some information to the hearer and seeks to convince the hearer of something [15,97]. What Fox meant by the question “Who cares?” was the statement statement “Nobody cares.”

d) Further on in Mitchell Wilson’s novel, Fox interviews Eric Gorin, a young scientist who applied for a job in his lab. Closing their conversation, Fox wants to show his friendliness by asking a formal personal question: "And did you have a pleasant summer, Mr. Gorin?”Its nonliteral meaning is that of a directive:
“Relax. Don’t be so tense.” Fox expects a conventional reply “Yes, thank you”, but Gorin’s utterance breaks the rules of speech etiquette: “A pleasant summer?” Erik was silent for the time of two long breaths. “No, sir,” he said explosively. “I damn well did not have a pleasant summer!” Fox is startled into silence: Gorin not only took the question literally, but did not follow the politeness principle as well.

e)“I'm not quite sure how long you've known the Fieldings” (J. Fowles); "I'm dying to know what you did with all the lions you slaughtered," said Susie Boyd (S. Maugham); “I'd like to know why she's gone off like this.” (J. Fowles).

Indirect questions in the utterances above are compound sentences whose principle clauses contain predicates of cognition while subordinate clauses specify the desired information.

f) Indirect speech acts are frequent when a person of a lower social status addresses a person of a higher social status. Often they contain additional markers of politeness like apologies, appellations to the hearer’s volition, etc. For instance, a maid says to her mistress: “I'm sorry to have disturbed you, Madam... I only wondered whether you wished to see me.” (D. du Maurier). A visitor says to his hostess:“I only want to know the truth, if you.will tell it to me” (E. Voynich).

g) “A question in a question” is also an indirect speech act. The speaker asks if the hearer is knowledgeable about something, and the informative question is included into the whole construction as a complement. Such utterances give the hearer a chance “to quit the game” by answering only the direct question, e.g."Do you happen to know when it is open?" - "Oh, no, no. I haven't been there myself" (L. Jones).

h) A reliable way to be polite is to express a communicative intention as a request to perform it. Such a request can be formulated as a separate utterance, a part of an utterance or a composite sentence, for instance: “May I ask you where you are staying?” (C. Snow); “Might I inquire if you are the owner?” (L. Jones); “What are your таin ideas so far, sir, if you don't mind me asking?” (K. Amis);“I should be very much obliged if you would tell me as exact as possible how Mrs. Haddo, died” (S. Maugham); “Would it bother you if I asked you a question about how you lost your job with Axminster?” (D. Francis).

i) A gradual transition from an indirect speech act complying with the politeness principle to an impolite direct speech act with the same illocutionary force is shown in an episode of the popular cartoon “Shrek”.After Shrek had rescued Princess Fiona from the dragon, the girl asked him to remove his helmet, so that he could kiss her:“You did it! You rescued me! The battle is over. You can remove your helmet now.”

The italicized utterance is an indirect speech act (a representative with the illocutionary force of a directive).

Shrek, however, is unwilling to put off his helmet: he does not want the girl to see that he is an ogre. To make him obey her, Fiona uses another indirect speech act: “Why not remove your helmet?” and then a rather impolite directive: “Remove it! Now!”

6.2. Publicism

Indirect speech acts are widely used in publicistic works when the speaker or the writer aims at convincing the interlocutor of something. A quotation from an article published by “The Times” dated June 12, 1999, exemplifies this:

“The claim that the Earl of Oxford, or Bacon, or any other grandee must have written “Shakespeare” seems to be born largely of a snobbish conviction that a provincial grammar-school boy could not have produced that corpus of world masterpieces. Yet outstanding literary achievement is more likely to come from such a background than any other.

With the exception of Byron and Shelley, all our greatest writers have been middle-class, and most of them provincials. If Marlowe, a Canterbury shoemaker’s son, could re-create the worlds of Edward II and Tamburlaine, why should not a Stratford glover’s son depict courtly life at large? The argument that it would take an aristocrat to know how royalty behaved and thought ignores the imaginative power of well-read genius.”

The journalist’s argument“The claim … seems to be born largely of a snobbish conviction that a provincial grammar school boy could not have produced that corpus of world masterpieces.” contains two speech acts. On the one hand, it is a representative giving a negative, critical appraisal. On the other hand, it is an indirect expressive (a protest).

The argument “If Marlowe, a Canterbury shoemaker’s son, could re-create the worlds of Edward II and Tamburlaine, why should not a Stratford glover’s son depict courtly life at large?” is another indirect speech act. Formally, it is a question, but in essence it is an indirect statement (a representative).

Another article in “The Times” of November 13, 1999 is devoted to the safety of flights of private airplanes:

“…Their central, and only, point is not an argument but a prejudice - that safety and private sector are incompatible. This is obviously wrong, as the impressive history of this country's airlines and airports makes plain”.

The utterance “It's not an argument, but a predjudice- that safety and private sector are incompatible”is a representative, but on the other hand, the author protests against the point of view taken by his opponents, and this utterance can also be regarded as an indirect expressive.

Evidently, indirect speech acts influence the quality of argumentation, and that is crucial for publicism. They amplify the speaker’s impact upon the hearers’ feelings and emotions.

6.3. Advertising

Indirect speech acts are widely used in advertising. Advertisements can perform various literal functions combining representatives (information on the product), commissives (safety or quality guarantee), expressives (admiration for the product), etc. But the pragmatic focus of any advertisement is always a directive: “Buy it now!”

For example, the advertisement: “You’ll see Tefal in action! Purchasing the new model, you get a present!” is a directive disguised as a commissive (a promise). Often the implication is biased from the product to its potential user, like in the slogan: “L’Oreal, Paris. Because I’m worth it” (a directive camouflaged as a representative).

6.4. Anecdotes

Indirect speech acts are often the heart of an anecdote [17]: Two businessmen made a fortune by means of forgery and were doing their best to be considered aristocrats. They even had their portraits painted by the most famous and “expensive” artist. The portraits were first displayed at a grand rout. The businessmen brought the most influential critic to the portraits hoping to hear the words of admiration and compliments. The critic stared at the portraits for a while, then shook his head as if something important were missing and asked pointing at the space between the portraits: “And where is the Savior?”

The implication of the question is unambiguous: Jesus Christ between the two robbers. The critic made up a complicated indirect speech act: he disguised an evaluative representative: “You are two scoundrels, of that I am sure” as a question “And where is the Savior?”

Anecdotes often play with a wrong understanding of the speaker’s illocutionary point by the hearer, for example:

Someone knocks at the window of a peasant’s house at 3 a.m.:

- Hey, you need any firewood?

- No, go away, I am sleeping.

In the morning, the peasant saw that all the firewood disappeared from his shed.  

In this funny story the peasant took the question for an offer, and his interlocutor (hardly by mistake) took the refusal as the answer.

7. INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS AS A YARDSTICK OF COMMUNICATIVE MATURITY AND MUTUAL UNDERSTANDING

                                                      “Нам не дано предугадать, как слово     

                                                        наше отзовется”.

                                                                                            Ф.Тютчев

   

Understanding of indirect speech acts is not a man’s inborn ability. Younger children whose communicational skills are not yet well developed perceive only one illocutionary force of a speech act, the one deducible from the syntactic form of an utterance.For instance, once my four-year-old son was carrying home a paintbrush I just bought for him. On our way home he often dropped it. I said: “You let your brush fall a hundred times!” meaning a directive: “Be more careful!” The boy, however, took my words literally and replied: “Of course not, mom. I dropped it only six times!”

Here is another example of communicational immaturity. A boy of seven phones to his mother’s office:

- I’d like to speak to Mrs. Jones, please.

-She is out. Please call back in a few minutes.

- OK.

The boy reacted to the utterance “Please call back in a few minutes” as to a request while the communicative situation required answering“Thank you” (for advice) instead of“OK”.

If the hearer does not recognize the speaker’s communicative intentions, a communicative failure will follow.For example, asking, “Where is the department store?” one may hear: “The department store is closed” in a situation when one needs the department store as an orienting point.

Quite often a question is understood as a reproach, e.g.

- Why didn’t you invite him?

- Invite him yourself if you want to.

- I do not want to invite him. I am just asking.

Surprise can be taken for distrust:

- Does it really cost that much?

- Don’t you believe me?

Sociolinguistic research shows that everywhere in the civilized world women tend to use more indirect speech acts than men. Educated people, regardless of their sex, prefer indirect speech acts to direct ones. Correct understanding of indirect speech acts by an adult is an index of his or her sanity [9,90].

On balance, the question How to do things with words?cannot be answered easily and unambiguously: just build your utterance in accordance with certain rules or use one of the “moulds”, and you will avoid a communication failure.

A chasm of incomplete understanding always separates communicants, even most intimate ones, and indirect speech acts often make it deeper. Yet, only words can bridge the chasm conducting the thought from one shore to the other. Every time the bridge is to be built from scratch, and choosing linguistic means, the interactants must take into account the distance, the “weather” conditions, the previous mistakes, both their own and other people’s, and “the weight” of the thought to be conveyed. Finally, the thought is worded and set off, but we can only guess what awaits it on the other shore. We are helpless there, and our thought is now in the hearer’s power.

CONCLUSIONS

Correspondence between the syntactic form of an utterance and its pragmatic function is not always 1:1. The same syntactic form can express various communicative intentions. On the other hand, to express a communicative intention we can use a variety of linguistic means. Therefore, inspeech there are many constructions used to express not the meaning fixed by the system of language, but a secondary meaning that is conventional or appears in a particular context. Speech acts made up by means of such constructions are indirect. In indirect speech acts, the speaker conveys the non-literal as well as the literal meaning, and an apparently simple utterance may, in its implications, count for much more.Hence, it is very important to study not only the structure of a grammatical or lexical unit and its meaning in the system of language, but also the pragmatic context shaping its functioning in communication.

A number of theories try to explain why we generate indirect speech acts and how we discover them in each other’s speech. The inference theory brought forward by John Searle claims that we first perceive the literal meaning of the utterance and find some indication that the literal meaning is inadequate. Having done that, we derive the relevant indirect force from the literal meaning and context.

Another line of explanation developed by Jerrold Sadock is that indirect speech acts are expressions based on an idiomatic meaning added to their literal meaning.

Jerry Morgan writes about two types of convention in indirect speech acts: conventions of language and conventions of usage. Conventions of usage express what Morgan calls "short-circuited implicatures": implicatures that once were motivated by explicit reasoning but which now do not have to be calculated explicitly anymore.

According to the relevance theory developed by Sperber and Wilson, the process of interpretation of direct speech acts does not at all differ from the process of interpretation of indirect speech acts. Furthermore, it is literal utterances that are often marked and sound less natural than utterances with indirect meaning.

Speech act theories have treated illocutionary acts as the products of single utterances based on single sentences with only one illocutionary point - thus becoming a pragmatic extension to sentence grammars. The contribution of the illocutions of individual utterances to the understanding of topics and episodes is not yet well documented.

Pragmatic research reveals that the main types of indirect speech acts are found in all natural languages. Yet, some indirect speech acts are specific for a group of languages or even for a particular language. Conventional indirect speech acts must always be taken into account when learning a foreign language. They often make the communicative center of utterances and sound much more natural than direct speech acts.

Indirect speech acts are widely used in everyday speech, in fiction, and in publicistic works because they influence the quality of argumentation and amplify the impact upon the hearer’s emotions.   Indirect speech acts are the driving force of advertisements whose illocutionary point is always a directive: "Buy it now!"

It has been found that indirect expressives, directives and representatives compose the most numerous group of indirect speech acts in modern English discourse.

The use of indirect speech acts in discourse has been studied by a number of linguists, cognitive scientists, and philosophers, including Searle [18], [19], [43], [44], [45];  Grice [4], [30];Ballmer [23]; Kreckel [34]; Clark [27]; Partridge  [40],   Cohen [28],   Pocheptsov [13], Romanov [16]. Yet, the research of indirect speech acts is still far from being complete.

РЕЗЮМЕ

Робота присвячена непрямим мовленнєвим актам у сучасному англійському дискурсі. Непрямі мовленнєві акти – це мовленнєві дії, що здійснюються за допомогою висловлювань, які мають дві іллокутивні сили, тобто мовець має на увазі одночасно і пряме значення висловлювання, і щось більше. Типові приклади непрямих мовленнєвих актів – це ввічливі прохання у вигляді запитань або твердження у вигляді запитань (риторичні питання). Непрямі мовленнєві акти привутні в усіх мовах, проте в кожній мові вони мають свої особливості.

Розділи 1 - 4 є теоретичними. У них розкривається сутність непрямих мовленнєвих актів, розглядаються причини їхньої широкої поширеності в мовленні на прикладі англійського дискурса, аналізуються існуючі теорії, що пояснюють механізм розуміння співрозмовниками непрямих мовленнєвих актів, з'ясовується внесок іллокутивної сили окремих висловлювань у процес розуміння усього дискурса.

Розділи 5 - 7 мають практичний характер. У них порівнюються конвенціональні непрямі мовленнєві актианглійської й української мов, що використовуються в типових ситуаціях спілкування; наводяться приклади непрямих мовленнєвих актів в творах сучасних британських і американських авторів, газетах, рекламних роликах; доводиться, що розуміння людиною непрямих мовленнєвих актів є мірилом його комунікативної зрілості. Особливо підкреслюється, що оскільки непрямі мовленнєві акти грають істотну роль у мовному впливі на співрозмовника, в етиці, у повсякденному спілкуванні і носять конкретномовний характер, їх необхідно враховувати при вивченні іноземних мов.

     

Ключові слова: непрямий мовленнєвий акт,   теорія мовленнєвих актів, текст, дискурс, локуція, іллокуція, перлокуція, комунікативний намір, принцип кооперації, принцип увічливості, іллокутивна сила, мовленнєва поведінка,комунікація, прагматика, контекст.

  

     

LITERATURE

      1. Богданов В.В. Речевое общение: прагматические и семантические аспекты.-Л.: Изд-во ЛГУ,1990. - 88 с.              

      2.Вежбицка А. Речевые акты // Новое в зарубежной лингвистике. Вип. 16.- М.: Прогресс, 1985. – С. 255-276.

     3.Голденков М. Осторожно Hot dog. Современный активный English. - М.: ЧеРо,1999. – 267 с.

     4.Грайс Г.П. Логика и речевое общение // Новое в зарубежной лингвистике.    Вип. 16. - М.: Прогресс, 1985. – С. 14-76.

     5.Деметрий. О стиле // Античные риторики. - М.:Изд-во МГУ         им.М.В.Ломоносова,1978. - С.235-285.

    6.Еремеев Я.Н. Директивные высказывания с точки зрения диалогического подхода // Теоретическая и прикладная лингвистика. Вип. 2. – Воронеж: видавничий центр ВГТУ, 2000.- с.109-126.

   7.   Клюев Е.В. Речевая коммуникация. М.: ПРИОР, 1998. – 175 с.

   8.   Конрад Р. Вопросительные предложения как косвенные речевые акты // 

Новое в зарубежной лингвистике. Вип. 16. М.: Прогресс, 1985. С. 349-384.

9.   Мартынюк А.П. О реализации принципа вежливости в речи женщин и         мужчин // Вестник Харьковского университета. Вып.339. Человек и речеваядеятельность. - Харьков,1989. - С.89-92.

10. Остин Дж. Слово как действие // Новое в зарубежной лингвистике. Вип. 17.          - М.: Прогресс, 1986. – С.38-94.

11. Петренко В.Ф. Проблемы эффективности речевого воздействия в аспекте       психолингвистики // Оптимизация речевого воздействия. - М.:Наука, 1990. –     С.18-31.

12. Петров С.С. Сложноподчиненные предложения с косвенным вопросом в       современном английском языке // Исследования по германской филологии. –       Кишинев: Мысль, 1975.– С.33-38.

13. Почепцов О.Г. Основы прагматического описания предложения. - Киев:       Вища школа,1986. - 116 с.

14.Пушкин А.А. Способ организации дискурса и типология языковых личностей // Язык, дискурс и личность: Сб.науч.тр. - Тверь: Изд-во Твер.ун-та,1990. - С.50-60.

15. Рестан П. Синтаксис вопросительного предложения.- М.: Высшая школа,       1972. – 183 с.

16. Романов А.А. Системный анализ регулятивных средств диалогического       общения. - М.:Инcтитут языкознания АН СССР,1988. - 183 с.

17. Руднев В. Словарь культуры ХХ века. –                  http://www.lib.ru/culture/RUDNEW/slowar. txt

18. Серль Дж. Р. Косвенные речевые акты // Новое в зарубежной лингвистике.        Вип. 17.- М.: Прогресс, 1986. – С. 195-283.

19. Серль Дж. Р. Классификация иллокутивных актов // Новое в зарубежной       лингвистике: Вип. 17. Теория речевых актов. - М.: Прогресс, 1986. – С. 170 – 195.

20. Allan K. Linguistic Meaning. - Vol.1. - London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,1986.       - 452 p.

21. Austin J.L. How to Do Things with Words. - Oxford: Oxford University         Press,1962. – 167 p.

22. Bach K.,Harnish R.Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts. - Cambridge:        MIT Press, 1979. – 217 p.

23. Ballmer T., Brennenstuhl W. Speech Act Classification: A Study in the Lexical       Analysis of English Speech Activity Verbs. - Berlin: Springer,1981. - 274 p.

24. Blum-Kulka Sh., Hause J., Kasper G. Investigating Cross-Cultural Pragmatics:      An Introductory Overview // Cross-Cultural Pragmatics: Requests and Apologies. Norwood: Ablex,1989. - P.1-34.

25. Bogardus E.S. Social Distance and its Practical Implications // Journal of        Sociology and Social Research 22. - 1988. - P.462-476.

26. Brown P., Levinson S. Politeness: Some Universals in Language Usage. –       Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,1987. - 345p.

27. Clark H.Arenas of language use. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1992. – 159 p.

28. Cohen G. Why is it Difficult to Put Names to Faces? // British Journal of       Psychology, N 81. - 1990. - P.287-297.

29. Edmondson W.J. On Saying You are Sorry // Conversational Routine.   - The       Hague: Mouton,1981. - P. 273-288.

30. Grice P.Presupposition and conversational implicature. Radical pragmatics, ed.       by Peter Cole, 183-98. New York: Academic Press, 1981. – 217 p.

31. House J., Kasper G. Politeness Markers in English and German // Conversational       Routine. F.Coulmas (Ed.). - The Hague: Mouton,1981. - P.157-186.

32. Hymes D. Models of the Interaction of Language and Social Life // Directions in       Sociolinguistics: the Ethnography of Communication. - New York: Holt, Rinehart       and Winston,1972. - P.35-71.

33. Kasper G. Linguistic Politeness: Current Research Issues // Journal of Pragmatics.      - 1990, No.2. - P.193-218.

34. Kreckel M. Communicative Acts and Shared Knowledge in Natural Discourse. –       London: Academic Press,1981. - 316 p.

35. Labov W., Fanshel D. Therapeutic Discourse: Psychotherapy as Conversation. –     New York: Academic Press,1977. - 392 p.

36. Leech G.N. Principles of Pragmatics. - London: Longman, 1983. - 250 p.

37. Levinson S.C. Pragmatics. - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,1983. -         420p.

38. Malinowski B. The Meaning of meaning. – London: Routledge, 1975.-  336p.       

39. Morgan J.Two types of convention in indirect speech acts // Syntax and        Semantics. – 1978. -Vol. 9: Pragmatics. – P. 261-280.

40. Partridge J.G. Semantic, Pragmatic and Syntactic Correlates: An Analysis of       Performative Verbs Based on English Data. - Tubingen: Narr,1982. - 172 p.

41. Russell B.On denoting. – London: Mind, 1957– 479 p.

42. Sadock J.Toward a linguistic theory of speech acts. New York:   Academic, 1974.- 353 p.

43. Searle J. R.Speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969.-120p.

44. Searle J. R.Expression and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University        Press, 1979 - 137p.

45. Searle J.R., Vanderveken D. Foundations of Illocutionary Logic. - Cambridge:       Cambridge University Press,1985. - 227 p.

46. Sperber, D., Wilson D.Relevance: Communication and cognition. -      Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986. – 210p.